Note
|
Terminology - ‘leftists’
My terminology in this article is not very precise. I don’t want to ostracize certain readers (‘leftists’) who I might agree with on many issues, so I might try to reword this in due course. In the meantime, please note that when I use the term ‘leftist’ I am referring to a distinctly ‘authoritarian’ breed of leftist — who is willing to violate real, natural rights to uphold their belief in imaginary rights (to goods and services — and ultimately to other people’s time and energy). For the time being please just forgive or overlook the looseness of the terminology. |
Motivation
It might seem like this article is making ‘much ado about nothing’, but if you spend half an hour — or even a few minutes — talking to an avowed ‘leftist’ or ‘statist’, you might quickly realise that the topic is potentially serious. The modern ‘leftist’ believes they are entitled to certain things, and by golly they will take almost any means necessary to procure them — even if that means trampling and desecrating people’s actual rights (which it probably will, sooner or later).
The political left are busy at work re-shaping society as they see fit — distorting and twisting important concepts such as ‘rights’ and ‘equality’ to bolster their purposes and agendas. I believe this is deeply disingenuous and insidious. The motivation of this article is to briefly bring this topic to people’s attention and help them understand it.
Conceptions of rights
There are, broadly speaking, two ways of looking at rights:
-
rights as actions - actions we can take which do not cause or initiate harm to other sentient beings, either directly (e.g. through physical violence) or indirectly (through damaging their environment)
-
rights as goods and services - perception of rights as ‘stuff’ that one can reasonably expect to be provided to them on the basis of their belonging to a community, to a nation state, or to human society period.
Natural Rights — rights as actions
In the first definition, a ‘right’ is simply any action which is not a ‘wrong’. Although this might seem like mere wordplay, it is actually a valuable way of looking at things. If a course of action causes no harm — directly or indirectly — to another sentient being, what grounds are there to prevent someone from pursuing it? Unless you subscribe to arbitrary religious edicts as a basis for morality, there aren’t any. Since we can’t think of a morally compelling reason to prevent someone from taking such an action, we might say that they have a ‘right’ to take it.
(It is worth considering here that — under this definition — our ‘rights’ are vast in number. I.e., the number of actions we can take which do not result in harm to others — and consequently the number of ‘rights’ we can exercise — are essentially uncountable.)
Social contracts and the right to inaction or non-participation
We are morally justified, also, in refusing to take certain actions, to refuse participation in certain enterprises, and to resist attempts at duress and coercion.
This is important because some people resort to the idea of an implicit ‘social contract’ to justify coercive mechanisms for achieving societal goals. The ‘social contract’ would be tenable if it was something that people willingly ‘signed up for’ — if it was based on meaningful informed agreement, and confined to limited geographical areas (e.g. towns or villages).
But this is not typically how ‘leftists’ understand a ‘social contract’; they view it as something which someone is ‘born into’ by merely being birthed within the boundaries of a particular nation state, and which one can not ‘opt out of’. (The argument that a person can ‘move to another country’ if they disagree with the social contract is debased; almost all nation states have adopted similar social contracts; and why should the ‘dissident’ — rather than the ‘statist’ — be the one to leave?)
Rights to goods and services? To other people’s labour?
The second view of rights mentioned above is a more modern incarnation. This view is that people have a ‘right’ to goods and services, or — on a more abstract level — to a certain ‘standard of living’. (Since a certain standard of living relies, ultimately, on the provision of goods and services to the person who enjoys that standard of living, this is essentially arguing the same thing.)
But goods and services require people’s time, energy, and labour for their provision. It is not possible to proclaim a ‘right’ to goods and services (e.g. education, health care or national defense) without introducing mechanisms in society to ensure that sufficient human labour, time and effort are directed and allocated towards these ends — to fulfilling these (theoretical) ‘rights’.
And this, in a way, is the crux of the matter. Such ‘mechanisms’ — whether taxation, conscription, or other forms of compulsory ‘public’ or ‘national service’ — invariably involve some form of duress, coercion or theft, and the violation of a person’s actual rights — including the right (alluded to above) to not participate in a system or enterprise which they do not believe in or does not align with their values.
Natural Rights and access to land
I mentioned above that goods require human input for their provision., but there is one exception to this: the land. Access to land is a prerequisite for the exercise of natural rights (to work, play, explore, feed oneself, etc.), and is ‘God-given’.
Many so-called ‘libertarians’, ‘conservatives’ and ‘anarcho-capitalists’ fail or refuse to acknowledge this fact, and contend, basically, that land is just another ‘good’ or ‘commodity’ to be ‘bought and sold’ willy-nilly. But it is largely meaningless — even nonsensical — to talk about rights (as actions) if one does not have a physical arena in which to exercise them.
Summary
Both the political left and right hold untenable views on rights. The left proclaims a right to ‘health care’, ‘education’, etc. — which tacitly sanctions the (metaphorical) holding of a gun to other people’s heads to fulfill these (so-called) ‘rights’. This is a profound and chronic delusion.
The political right — in refusing to recognize or acknowledge the ‘land problem’, and to respect the ‘Lockean proviso’ (essentially that one should ony lay claim to as much land as one can reasonably use — and leave enough for others) — makes a mockery of all their other arguments regarding natural rights (which are otherwise reasonable).
Comments
No comments yet.